In mathematics, in the area of additive number theory, the Erdős–Fuchs theorem is a statement about the number of ways that numbers can be represented as a sum of elements of a given additive basis, stating that the average order of this number cannot be too close to being a linear function.
The theorem is named after Paul Erdős and Wolfgang Heinrich Johannes Fuchs, who published it in 1956.
be an infinite subset of the natural numbers and
its representation function, which denotes the number of ways that a natural number
can be expressed as the sum of
(taking order into account).
We then consider the accumulated representation function
which counts (also taking order into account) the number of solutions to
The theorem then states that, for any given
log ( n
satisfying the above estimate.
The Erdős–Fuchs theorem has an interesting history of precedents and generalizations.
In 1915, it was already known by G. H. Hardy[2] that in the case of the sequence
of perfect squares one has
log ( n
This estimate is a little better than that described by Erdős–Fuchs, but at the cost of a slight loss of precision, P. Erdős and W. H. J. Fuchs achieved complete generality in their result (at least for the case
Another reason this result is so celebrated may be due to the fact that, in 1941, P. Erdős and P. Turán[3] conjectured that, subject to the same hypotheses as in the theorem stated, the relation
could not hold.
This fact remained unproven until 1956, when Erdős and Fuchs obtained their theorem, which is even stronger than the previously conjectured estimate.
This theorem has been extended in a number of different directions.
In 1980, A. Sárközy[4] considered two sequences which are "near" in some sense.
He proved the following: In 1990, H. L. Montgomery and R. C. Vaughan[5] were able to remove the log from the right-hand side of Erdős–Fuchs original statement, showing that
cannot hold.
In 2004, Gábor Horváth[6] extended both these results, proving the following: The natural generalization to Erdős–Fuchs theorem, namely for
, is known to hold with same strength as the Montgomery–Vaughan's version.
In fact, M. Tang[7] showed in 2009 that, in the same conditions as in the original statement of Erdős–Fuchs, for every
cannot hold.
In another direction, in 2002, Gábor Horváth[8] gave a precise generalization of Sárközy's 1980 result, showing that Yet another direction in which the Erdős–Fuchs theorem can be improved is by considering approximations to
In 1963, Paul T. Bateman, Eugene E. Kohlbecker and Jack P. Tull[9] proved a slightly stronger version of the following: At the end of their paper, it is also remarked that it is possible to extend their method to obtain results considering
, but such results are deemed as not sufficiently definitive.