Smn theorem

In computability theory the S mn  theorem, written also as "smn-theorem" or "s-m-n theorem" (also called the translation lemma, parameter theorem, and the parameterization theorem) is a basic result about programming languages (and, more generally, Gödel numberings of the computable functions) (Soare 1987, Rogers 1967).

It was first proved by Stephen Cole Kleene (1943).

The name S mn  comes from the occurrence of an S with subscript n and superscript m in the original formulation of the theorem (see below).

In practical terms, the theorem says that for a given programming language and positive integers m and n, there exists a particular algorithm that accepts as input the source code of a program with m + n free variables, together with m values.

This algorithm generates source code that effectively substitutes the values for the first m free variables, leaving the rest of the variables free.

The smn-theorem states that given a function of two arguments

which is computable, there exists a total and computable function such that

basically "fixing" the first argument of

It's like partially applying an argument to a function.

In other words, it addresses the idea of "parametrization" or "indexing" of computable functions.

It's like creating a simplified version of a function that takes an additional parameter (index) to mimic the behavior of a more complex function.

is designed to mimic the behavior of

Essentially, by selecting the right values for

behave like for a specific computation.

Instead of dealing with the complexity of

that captures the essence of the computation.

The basic form of the theorem applies to functions of two arguments (Nies 2009, p. 6).

of recursive functions, there is a primitive recursive function s of two arguments with the following property: for every Gödel number p of a partial computable function f with two arguments, the expressions

are defined for the same combinations of natural numbers x and y, and their values are equal for any such combination.

In other words, the following extensional equality of functions holds for every x: More generally, for any m, n > 0, there exists a primitive recursive function

of m + 1 arguments that behaves as follows: for every Gödel number p of a partial computable function with m + n arguments, and all values of x1, …, xm: The function s described above can be taken to be

Given arities m and n, for every Turing Machine

, there exists a Turing machine

of arity n, such that Furthermore, there is a Turing machine S that allows k to be calculated from x and y; it is denoted

Informally, S finds the Turing Machine

that is the result of hardcoding the values of y into

The result generalizes to any Turing-complete computing model.

This can also be extended to total computable functions as follows: Given a total computable function

There is also a simplified version of the same theorem (defined infact as "simplified smn-theorem", which basically uses a total computable function as index as follows: Let

There, there is a total computable function