Foundations of statistics

[7] Although a hybrid approach combining elements of both methods is commonly taught and utilized, the philosophical questions raised during the debate still remain unresolved.

[citation needed] Publications by Fisher, like "Statistical Methods for Research Workers" in 1925 and "The Design of Experiments" in 1935,[8] contributed to the popularity of significance testing, which is a probabilistic approach to deductive inference.

[citation needed] One common application of this method is to determine whether a treatment has a noticeable effect based on a comparative experiment.

Neyman and Pearson collaborated on the problem of selecting the most appropriate hypothesis based solely on experimental evidence, which differed from significance testing.

Their most renowned joint paper, published in 1933,[9] introduced the Neyman-Pearson lemma, which states that a ratio of probabilities serves as an effective criterion for hypothesis selection (with the choice of the threshold being arbitrary).

In the current environment, the concept of Type II errors are used in power calculations for confirmatory hypothesis tests' sample size determination.

During this exchange, Fisher also discussed the requirements for inductive inference, specifically criticizing cost functions that penalize erroneous judgments.

In 1938, Neyman relocated to the West Coast of the United States of America, effectively ending his collaboration with Pearson and their work on hypothesis testing.

Neyman-Pearson hypothesis testing made significant contributions to decision theory, which is widely employed, particularly in statistical quality control.

Hypothesis testing remains a subject of controversy for some users, but the most widely accepted alternative method, confidence intervals, is based on the same mathematical principles.

Due to the historical development of testing, there is no single authoritative source that fully encompasses the hybrid theory as it is commonly practiced in statistics.

Empirical evidence indicates that individuals, including students and instructors in introductory statistics courses, often have a limited understanding of the meaning of hypothesis testing.

[19] Two distinct interpretations of probability have existed for a long time, one based on objective evidence and the other on subjective degrees of belief.

Classical inferential statistics emerged primarily during the second quarter of the 20th century,[6] largely in response to the controversial principle of indifference used in Bayesian probability at that time.

[5] While Fisher had a unique interpretation of probability that differed from Bayesian principles, Neyman adhered strictly to the frequentist approach.

In the realm of Bayesian statistical philosophy, mathematics, and methods, de Finetti,[21] Jeffreys,[22] and Savage[23] emerged as notable contributors during the 20th century.

Savage played a crucial role in popularizing de Finetti's ideas in English-speaking regions and establishing rigorous Bayesian mathematics.

For three generations, statistics have progressed significantly, and the views of early contributors are not necessarily considered authoritative in present times.

Frequentist inference incorporates various perspectives and allows for scientific conclusions, operational decisions, and parameter estimation with or without confidence intervals.

By applying Bayes' theorem, a more abstract concept is introduced, which involves estimating the probability of a hypothesis (associated with a theory) given the data.

For instance, Stein's paradox highlights the intricacy of determining a "flat" or "uninformative" prior probability distribution in high-dimensional spaces.

[2] While Bayesians perceive this as tangential to their fundamental philosophy, they find frequentist plagued with inconsistencies, paradoxes, and unfavorable mathematical behavior.

Classical statistics, with its reliance on mechanical calculators and specialized printed tables, boasts a longer history of obtaining results.

Bayesian methods, on the other hand, have shown remarkable efficacy in analyzing sequentially sampled information, such as radar and sonar data.

Several Bayesian techniques, as well as certain recent frequentist methods like the bootstrap, necessitate the computational capabilities that have become widely accessible in the past few decades.

There is an ongoing discourse regarding the integration of Bayesian and frequentist approaches,[25] although concerns have been raised regarding the interpretation of results and the potential diminishment of methodological diversity.

Bayesians share a common stance against the limitations of frequent, but they are divided into various philosophical camps (empirical, hierarchical, objective, personal, and subjective), each emphasizing different aspects.

The likelihood principle's staunchest proponents argue that it provides a more solid foundation for statistics compared to the alternatives presented by Bayesian and frequentist approaches.

[41] While Bayesian recognize the importance of likelihood for calculations, they contend that the posterior probability distribution serves as the appropriate basis for inference.

Bayesian statistics, on the other hand, interpret new observations based on prior knowledge, assuming continuity between the past and present.