Well-ordering principle

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty subset of nonnegative integers contains a least element.

[1] In other words, the set of nonnegative integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which

and some nonnegative integer (other orderings include the ordering

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem".

On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers

contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second-order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem.

For example: In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set

, assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample.

Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction.

This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction.

It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method[citation needed] and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

The well-ordering principle can be used in the following proofs.

Theorem: Every integer greater than one can be factored as a product of primes.

This theorem constitutes part of the Prime Factorization Theorem.

Proof (by well-ordering principle).

be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes.

Assume for the sake of contradiction that

Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element

By the definition of non-prime numbers,

is the smallest element of

can be factored as products of primes, where

Suppose for the sake of contradiction that the above theorem is false.

Then, there exists a non-empty set of positive integers

By the well-ordering principle,

has a minimum element

, the equation is false, but true for all positive integers less than

which shows that the equation holds for

So, the equation must hold for all positive integers.