Predication (philosophy)

[1] A comprehensive conceptualization describes it as the understanding of the relation expressed by a predicative structure primordially (i.e. both originally and primarily) through the opposition between particular and general or the one and the many.

[3] Predication emerged when ancient philosophers began exploring reality and the two entities that divide it: properties and the things that bear them.

It was argued that the relationship resembled the logical analysis of a sentence wherein the division of subject and predicate arises spontaneously.

[6] They hold that a number has an independent reality, arguing that substances such as fire and water were not the real essences of the things they are predicated.

[6] In describing Greek philosophy, Charles Kahn identified predication as one of the three concepts - along with truth and reality - that ontology connected.

[8] In Grundlagen, for instance, Gottlob Frege used this term to state that a statement of a number contains a predication about a concept.

Heyse's Deutsche Grammatik (1814), which influenced the development of the Japanese notion of predication called chinjutsu.

[9] Chinjutsu would later be explored by other Japanese logicians such as Takeo Miyake, Minoru Watanabe, and Motoki Tokieda.

[13] In Fregean semantics, predication is described as the relation where "an argument saturates an open position in the function, cf.

[15] He maintained that predicates do not name, stand for, or rely on the existence of abstract entities (e.g. properties, relations, sets).

[3] Aquinas also proposed other types of predication such as negative and affirmative, categorical and hypothetical, in necessary and contingent matter, and universal and particular, among others.

Plato and Aristotle used predication to address the Problem of Universals .
The Predication of Saint Paul